Ethics and the Triage Model in Managed Care Hospital Psychiatry
by Harold J. Bursztajn, M.D., Thomas G. Gutheil, M.D., and Archie
Brodsky
One manifestation of the health care cost-consciousness and substantial
control that managed care organizations exercise over clinical practice
(Schreter et al., 1997) has been the increasing
use of the concept of triage as a rationale for clinical decisions. In
its original battlefield context, triage (a French word meaning
sorting or choice selection) has been defined as follows: The evaluation
and classification of casualties for purposes of treatment and evacuation.
It is based on the principle of accomplishing the greatest good for the
greatest number of wounded and injured men in the special circumstances
of warfare at a particular time. The decision which must be made concerns
the need for resuscitation, the need for emergency surgery and the futility
of surgery because of the intrinsic lethality of the wound. Sorting also
involves the establishment of priorities for treatment and evacuation
(U. S. Department of Defense, 1975).
Triage commonly entails dividing those seeking treatment into three categories:
-
those who are so well off that they do not need treatment or can
wait to be treated;
-
those who are so severely wounded that they have little hope of survival
even with treatment; and
-
those whose chances of survival would be significantly improved by
timely treatment (U. S. Department of
Defense, 1975).
Traditionally associated with military and civilian disaster medicine,
triage has become an established and recommended clinical procedure in
hospital emergency rooms and other general medical settings (Vickery,
1975; Rund and Rausch, 1981). As such, it has
had considerable appeal for understaffed, underfunded mental health centers
where staff members perceive themselves to be, and commonly are, embattled
and besieged by sheer numbers of patients. Triage has been seen by some
observers to be helpful in mental health settings (Edelwich
and Brodsky, 1980).
However, the clinical and ethical pitfalls of the application of the
triage model are perhaps even greater in psychiatry than in general medicine,
since clinicians' and patients' emotional reactions to one another play
a vital and much discussed role in the treatment of mental illness. For
this very reason, psychiatry, with its awareness of such interpersonal
dynamics, is equipped to critically evaluate the impact of this form
of decision making and its potential pitfalls in other areas of medicine,
where interpersonal dynamics have real, if less well understood, effects
on illness and treatment (Bursztajn et al., 1981).
Here we shall examine how group process, evoked hostility and patients'
repetition compulsions can contribute to the misuse of triage in inpatient
psychiatry, and how such misuse can be observed and prevented.
Triage as a Decision Rule: Ethical Implications
Triage represents a modification of the simple decision rule: the greater
the need, the greater the resources to be applied. Triage reasoning follows
this rule up to a point-the point where a patient's ability to survive
(or to benefit from treatment) becomes seriously open to question. Once
that critical threshold is reached, the triage principle calls for the
application of fewer rather than more resources to the care of that patient.
In triage situations, a patient in extremis might be denied treatment
on the grounds that a disproportionate expenditure of limited resources
to save one patient would cause more damage to other patients (in the
aggregate).
In a sudden disaster, where there are many simultaneous casualties and
the resources at hand are obviously limited, the need for such tragic
choices is incontestable (Calabresi and Bobbitt,
1978); catastrophic circumstances justify judiciously callous choices.
However, to invoke the triage model to justify individual treatment decisions
in a stable clinical setting-under stressful but not catastrophic circumstances-such
as a mental health facility, raises, serious ethical questions (O'Donnell,
1960; Lucas, 1975; Childress,
1978; Winslow, 1982).
In the first place, the judgment that a patient is beyond help is inevitably
a probabilistic one. Like any other clinical judgment, it is a question
not of absolute certainty, but of a greater or lesser degree of certainty
(Bursztajn et al., 1981). Triage decisions are
made on the basis of such implicitly probabilistic judgments; for example,
that there is a 90%, 95% or 99% probability that a patient "cannot
survive" or "cannot improve." To balance such estimates
against the probabilities of saving other patients, as well as to compare
the value of the lives saved or enhanced in each case, is a delicate
matter. Moreover, while the anticipated outcome (i.e., nonsurvival or
nonimprovement) is not absolutely certain to occur, the assumption that
it will occur may become a self-fulfilling prophecy.
The decision to treat a patient as hopeless may (for whatever combination
of organic and psychological reasons) close the gap from, say, a 95%
to a 100% probability of a tragic outcome. Just as in Paris before World
War I, the word triage was used to mean the sorting out and throwing
away of wilted or dead produce (Rund and Rausch, 1981).
Today there is cause for concern that the labeling of people as dead
(or its equivalent) will leave them fit only for discard. The study of
the psychology of survival in the Holocaust confirms that people who
are labeled as dead either by themselves or by others tend to engage
in a powerful form of socially self-fulfilling prophecies (O'Keefe,
1982; Bettelheim, 1960; Des
Pres, 1976).
Finally, we need to ask whether our moral responsibility toward individual
patients extends beyond "accomplishing the greatest good for the
greatest number" (United States Department
of Defense, 1975). Maximizing the total benefits experienced by all
patients is a useful decision rule, but it is not a fully sufficient
one in a society that values the rights of minorities, including the
smallest minority: the individual. Health care institutions are to be
judged not only by how well they serve patients in the aggregate, but
also by how well they discharge their special duties on behalf of the
worst off, the most unfortunate.
Thus, while acknowledging the fact of limited resources and the need
for decision rules that (when necessary) take the limits into account,
we must also guard against automatically resorting to triage reasoning.
Sensible on its face, the decision rule signified by the word triage
does not encompass all of the ethical issues involved in the allocation
of treatment resources to patients. Moreover, it is subject to misuse
(that is, overuse) in the context of the strong negative feelings characteristically
evoked by psychiatric patients requiring inpatient hospitalization, that
is, mentally ill patients who have already alienated themselves from
one social support system.
Unlikability Versus Pathology
The question of triage takes on added significance in the mental health
area in the interpretation of mental illness as a consequence of losing
out in the struggle for existence (Sloman, 1981).
In this view, a person who has been branded by the family as the cause
of its problems often provokes, in a compulsive repetition, the same
unintentional scape-goating in other social contexts. Extruded by the
family and then by society, the mentally ill patient projects unlikability
yet again in the hospital as a means of warding off aloneness and fear
of the unfamiliar by recreating familiar (in this case pathological)
object ties in the new setting.
The institutionalized mentally ill are thus inherently susceptible to
the prejudicial implications of triage. Indeed, unlikability itself can
function in practice as a partial definition of mental illness, as shown
by findings that the patients found unlikable by resident physicians
tend to be judged to be in need of commitment (Hamm et
al., 1983); that patients who elicit negative reactions from interviewers
are most likely to commit suicide (Motto et al., 1981); and by Havens'
own clinical description of the unlikability projected by a suicidal
patient (Havens, 1965).
Given the close connection between unlikability and pathology in the
patient, the use of triage reasoning by the clinician must always be
examined as a possible expression of the powerful negative feelings patients
can stir up in clinicians (Groves, 1978). It may
also serve as a rationalization for projecting onto the patient what
is felt to be unsatisfactory in oneself (Klein, 1975).
In analytic terms, these universal negative reactions-an inevitable part
of the therapeutic process-are referred to as "countertransference
hate" (Maltsberger and Buie, 1974).
Experienced clinicians are familiar with trainees' reactions to deep-seated
pathology and chronicity, such as "All the patients on this ward
are hopeless," or "This patient is too difficult for me to
learn from." Such resistance to full therapeutic engagement with
the mentally ill can take many forms, including diversionary preoccupations
with therapeutic ideology (Gutheil, 1977) or
forensic issues (Gutheil, 1979). Premature resort
to triage can be another mechanism of this normal resistance, and not
just for the neophyte, since it provides an acceptable outlet for uncomfortable,
guilt-arousing feelings.
The following case study exemplifies these dynamics:
Case 1: In a state-funded mental health center that has
undergone reorganization so as to decrease the number of available inpatient
beds, the case of a chronically ill, recalcitrant, assaultive patient
is presented at an ethics case conference. A resident in psychiatry who
is involved in the case asks whether, in the light of the limited resources
now available in the hospital, this patient should continue to be treated
at the expense of other patients. The patient is a 29-year-old man who
has been hospitalized for eight months. He has a sister who, after a
prolonged period of hospitalization, has been progressing well outside
the hospital for 10 years.
In the interview conducted at the conference, the patient's pathology
is traced to a pattern of interaction within the family. The patient's
parents were survivors of the Holocaust. His mother, preoccupied with
his identical twin with meningocele, gave the patient little attention.
His father, identifying with the Nazi oppressors, would beat him. The
patient in turn identifies with the angry, sadistic father and assaults
people (including other patients in the hospital). He is driven by his
identification with his parents' "survival guilt" with reference
to the Holocaust (Russell, 1980; Chodoff,
1980), together with his own particular survival guilt brought on
by having avoided the trauma of his defective twin.
In seeking to expel the patient, staff members defend as best they can
against the helplessness they feel in the patient's presence by introjecting
his projections and becoming the oppressive father that the patient's
survival guilt demands. In feeling overwhelmed with the patient, the
staff takes over the role of the mother who, herself overwhelmed, directs
her feelings not at the sick twin or at her explosive, unpredictable
husband, but at the physically healthy twin, the patient.
As a result, the staff declares the patient to be treatment-resistant
without ever having tried several potentially applicable treatment modalities.
These might include intensive psychotherapy and a focus on the therapeutic
alliance and limit-setting in the milieu, as well as more vigorous psychopharmacological
intervention on an individual level and a review of the pathological
dynamics in the hospital milieu on an interpersonal level. Instead, the
staff moves prematurely, albeit understandably, to a concern with the
patient's "environmental impact." The issue of scarcity of
resources is thus raised in connection with a patient whose parents did
indeed live under conditions of scarcity.
In addition to the patient's repetition compulsion and the hostile feelings
it evokes in clinicians, a case such as this can also be understood in
terms of group dynamics, such as those observed in group psychotherapy
(Yalom, 1975; Day, 1981). Attempts
to expel an individual by a group are common and occur in the face of
perceived scarcity, as when a group becomes too large for intimacy. The
individual chosen to be expelled may be one who is close at hand, one
who is unable to resist expulsion or one who has a distinguishing feature
which thereby becomes obnoxious to the group. When a patient is "triaged
out" of a hospital setting on insufficient grounds, such dynamics
may be found to operate among both patients and staff.
Common Variations
In order to avoid the misuse of triage, clinicians should be familiar
with the different ways in which evoked hostility (countertransference)
acts in combination with patient pathology and group process. The dynamics
leading to the inappropriate application of the triage model may originate
with the patient or with the staff or may represent an interaction between
the two.
In the patient-centered variation, a known or unknown pathology defeats
all possible modes of treatment, as in the following example:
Case 2: A burly male patient has an uncontrollable seizure
disorder not responsive to any known anticonvulsant. A major symptom
of this disorder is sudden episodes of violence, after which the patient
is post-ictal (i.e., in an altered state of consciousness that follows
seizures) and amnesic regarding his actions during the seizure. Staff
and other patients are extremely frightened of this man, particularly
because the usual measures of controlling medications, restraint and
seclusion are ineffective. When he is transferred to a higher security
setting, everyone is relieved.
In the staff-centered variation, countertransference is the driving force
of the patient's expulsion (Groves, 1978), as in
the following case, when a staff member provokes the patient's assault:
Case 3: A tense, withdrawn man is admitted to the ward.
One of the newer attendants, unfamiliar with interpersonal issues in
working with seriously ill patients, takes an instantaneous dislike to
the patient. This feeling is based on a coincidence, namely, that the
patient reminds the attendant of a sadistic older brother who used to
abuse him viciously over a number of years. The attendant, however, is
unaware of this unconscious factor. Nevertheless, he begins to provoke
the patient with increasing intensity. Over the next week the patient
remains aloof, though increasingly restless. Then, after a several-hour
period in which the attendant has roughed him up, taunted and mocked
him, and threatened him with various punishments, the patient explodes.
In the resulting scuffle, several staff are injured. The patient is transferred
to a security setting, while the dominant feeling on the ward is bewilderment
over what went wrong.
In the interactive variation, the patient and staff member(s), frightened
of each other, engage in mutually escalating provocations, as in the
following case:
Case 4: A patient is admitted with a diagnosis of schizophrenia,
paranoid type. His chief complaints include the idea that voices are
calling him homosexual and prompting homosexual acts. His therapist,
a resident who is struggling with his own homosexual impulses, encounters
difficulty setting useful limits with the patient. Deprived of needed
external controls, the patient becomes more anxious, decompensates further
and attacks male staff whom he perceives either as threatening, or attempting
to seduce him. After some period of time in this state, he is transferred.
The resident's relief contagiously affects the staff who, sensing the
problem and feeling intuitively that the issue is a conflicted one, have
been hesitant to confront the resident about his poor limit-setting.
These examples form a spectrum of cases which the clinician may experience
and should be able to recognize and distinguish from one another.
Mechanisms of Evoked Hostility (Countertransference)
There are numerous ways in which the vicissitudes of inadvertent hostility
toward patients (clinical countertransference) can subvert the use of
triage by mental health personnel. The forms of countertransference (as
seen by the dynamically oriented psychiatrist) that affect triage decisions
can, however, be grouped into two main categories: milieu countertransference,
whereby the clinician misperceives the clinical setting as one that requires
triage decisions; and individual countertransference, whereby the clinician
misjudges what triage category a particular patient falls into. Although
there is no hard-and-fast line separating milieu countertransference
from individual countertransference, the key distinction is between clinicians'
reactions to the milieu as a whole and to individual patients.
Milieu Countertransference
Helplessness in the face of chronic illness. Staff members may
incorrectly declare a state of limited resources in response to the helplessness,
frustration and reduced self-esteem brought on by treating the chronically
mentally ill.
Hostility evoked by violent or self-destructive patients. Staff members'
anxieties about their own safety and survival in the midst of violent,
self-destructive patients may resolve themselves into countertransference
(Groves, 1978; Maltsberger
and Buie, 1974) which, together with survival guilt (Modell, in press),
may motivate an appeal for triage. There is, of course, a place for rational
fear when coping with patients who act out violently. At the same time,
there is a substantial risk that clinicians will overreact.
Overidentification with patients' feelings. Here the staff internalizes
the patients' feelings of helplessness, hopelessness and guilt, and declares
a crisis where none exists.
Individual Countertransference
Concentration is on the least difficult patients. Staff members
may unconsciously respond to the helplessness and reduced self-esteem
brought on by the frustrations of patient care by pouring their therapeutic
energies only into those patients who show the quickest response to treatment-in
those who, in terms of triage, need treatment the least.
Overidentification with healthier patients. Treatment staff
may overidentify with the interests of healthier patients, whom they
see as more like themselves (Freud, 1957), rather
than with the most seriously ill patients, who serve as distressing reminders
of the clinician's own vulnerability to psychic disturbance and even
mortality (Modell, in press; White,
1977; Deutsch, 1965; Winnicott,
1965).
Rejection of most difficult patients. The hostility evoked by
difficult patients may lead the clinician to deny treatment to those
patients on grounds of triage even when they can be helped (Groves,
1978).
Mislabeling of patients as beyond help A patient who causes
or appears to cause hopelessness in the milieu (including the staff)
may, for that reason, be dismissed as a hopeless case.
Mislabeling of patients as needing continuing help. When resources
are indeed scarce and triage is called for, patients who provoke guilt
and the consequent reaction formation may be kept in the hospital longer
than they need to be, to the detriment of other patients.
Even when the most obvious errors are avoided, it remains difficult to
disentangle the effects of countertransference from the legitimate uses
of triage. Triage has great appeal for the clinician because it serves
as both a prima facie scientific decision-making rule (an ego ideal)
and an ethical guide for justifying actions with potentially tragic consequences
(a superego demand). Thus, for two of the "best" of motives,
clinicians risk premature cognitive closure (Chanowitz
and Langer, 1981), as when the statement "we need to triage" is
used to close discussion. Such closure prevents the deep thought and
reflection needed to ensure that triage is used rationally rather than
as rationalization.
Adverse Effects of Triage on Patients and Staff
Even when the shift from individual clinical considerations to environmental
impact is made on reasonable grounds, losses are suffered in the process.
In focusing on the well-being of the ward or facility as a whole, staff
members may inadvertently distance themselves from the individual patient.
This distancing reinforces and exacerbates the patient's inability to
learn the basic human skill of survival through cooperation. By appearing
to be unlikable, the mentally ill patient cuts himself or herself off
from the object ties (e.g., family, friends) that would allow for independent-that
is, interdependent-survival.
The patient accomplishes this in several ways: by failing to present
positive traits with which clinicians can identify, by presenting negative
traits with which clinicians would rather not identify and by rejecting
the clinician's offer to the patient of the best part of the clinician's
self that is presented in a helping relationship. Among the pitfalls
of triage, then, is its unwitting use in the service of the patient's
pathology.
Triage decisions also have practical consequences for patients which
must be considered in an overall cost/benefit analysis. Patients who
are declared untreatable and/or a threat to other patients are generally
transferred out to less stimulating settings (e.g., the chronic ward).
Moreover, discontinuity of care carries with it costs of its own. No
matter how scrupulously the referrals and terminations are carried out,
rejection and abandonment will be felt. While referrals or transfers
are sometimes necessary and may be beneficial to the patient in question
as well as to the milieu, they should be undertaken only with a clear
awareness of the projected benefits needed to justify these costs (President's
Commission, 1983).
Finally, it is not the patient alone who suffers, as the analogy with
group therapy suggests (Yalom, 1975). When a therapy
group extrudes one of its members, the initial relief experienced by
the group dissipates in the face of guilt at the surrender of pathology
together with a recognition of the missed opportunity to work through
the conflicts reawakened in group members by the "difficult" or "intolerable" member.
It seems reasonable to believe that the indiscriminate resort to triage
may have similar effects on both the patients and staff of the institutions
where it takes place. The same issues are at stake for society as a whole
in the current triaging of resources away from health care for the most
needy in favor of other public and private agendas (President's
Commission, 1983). Ironically, since psychiatric patients are seen
as having either intractable or self-remitting illnesses, a skepticism
about the efficacy of psychiatric intervention has led to a reduction
of resources allocated to mental health care, justified by resort to
the triage model itself.
Discussion
The transplantation of the triage model from wartime to peacetime conditions
necessitates reevaluation of its ethical foundations. "Scarce resources" in
a psychiatric hospital is not the same thing as in military or civilian
disaster medicine. Triage can be a valuable heuristic, but it must be
applied in the context of other heuristics if its pitfalls are to be
minimized. Ethical heuristics can be useful checks on the misapplication
of the triage rule. The best antidote to the uncritical use of triage
is a high degree of precision in framing the choices involved. Framing
these choices requires self-knowledge and self-scrutiny as to the feelings
that difficult patients arouse. Ethical analysis is helpful at this point
both as a process for detached empirical description and as a source
of principles for evaluating clinical alternatives.
Triage is not in itself a moral imperative, but rather a strategy to
serve the larger purpose of healing and reducing suffering in limited
resource settings. Moral principles that are relevant to triage include
the principles of beneficence, respect for persons and justice. According
to the principle of beneficence, we are to avoid harming other persons
and to help them where possible. Ordinarily the duty to avoid harm to
particular, identifiable individuals is more stringent than the duty
to promote the hypothetical or potential well-being of others.
The principle of beneficence suggests that vigilance is needed to ensure
that the catch-phrase "limited resources" does not go unchallenged,
for example, at case conferences as an all-purpose justification for
the avoidance of difficult clinical issues. How are the resources of
the ward or facility limited? By what measure? How and to what extent
will the continued treatment of a particular patient strain those resources?
It is essential, in other words, to specify concretely how one patient
can be experienced as taking the bread out of other patients' mouths
and whether the experience has a counterpart in clinical reality. For
example, in Case 1 it must be asked whether this experience is instead
the product of a reenactment of the patient's survivor guilt, with the
milieu staff cast unwittingly in the role of the family members who experience
a threat to their survival and therefore react punitively (Russell,
1980).
Similarly, the claim that a patient is untreatable must be subjected
to the same critical scrutiny under conditions of triage as in any other
clinical situation. In this way, ethical analysis serves self-analysis,
and vice-versa. It is to be assumed that countertransference operates
in the triage situation as it does in other clinical interactions and
must therefore be made accessible to self-analysis and dialogue. If triage
is to be used ethically, clinicians must be responsible for identifying
and working through the evoked hostility and other disruptive feelings
that may arise.
The principle of respect for persons suggests that, although triage is
commonly assumed to be equivalent to cost-benefit analysis, it actually
involves a more fundamental view of persons and rights. Triage can be
usefully understood as a tension between two sets of rights: the right
of the patient in question to receive adequate treatment, and the right
of other patients not to have therapeutic risks taken on behalf of that
patient at their expense. In addition, clinicians who work with violent
patients have a right to protect themselves. All too often, however,
a careless rush to self-protection carries a higher than necessary price
with respect to both the clinician's freedom to treat and the patient's
right to treatment.
Respect for persons means that persons are to be treated as ends in themselves
rather than as means to the achievement of others' welfare, or simply
as units in a cost-benefit equation. Moreover, as the principle of beneficence
suggests, the prevention of outright harm done by one patient to others
should be seen as a stronger justification for denial of treatment than
a concern with the possible depletion of resources available to other
patients.
Justice, understood as fairness in the distribution of benefits and burdens
within a community, requires that unequal allocation of clinical resources
be justified with reference to the welfare of the least advantaged patients.
One rule of thumb is to ask how any decision regarding the care of this
patient will impact on the resources available not only for the care
of the "average" patient, but also for the care of the least
fortunate or most difficult patient. Alternatively, one may avoid the
pitfalls of overidentification with the healthier patients' interests
by asking oneself whether one would still be making the triage decision
in question if one were playing a lottery where a possible outcome was
to share the identified triage patient's fate (Rawls,
1971).
For triage to be transplanted into the psychiatric setting, attention
to its excesses and abuses is a prerequisite for the possibility of its
ethical use.
(The authors wish to acknowledge the influence of dialogues with Sissela
Bok, Ph.D., and Leston L. Havens, M.D., on the ideas presented. Some
of the themes have been introduced in the authors' earlier work including "Use
and Misuse of the Triage Principle in the Management of Difficult Psychiatric
Inpatients" [unpublished manuscript, 1985] and Kaplan E, Bursztajn
HJ, Alexander V et al. Making treatment decisions. In: Gutheil T, Bursztajn
HJ, Brodsky A et al. [1991], Decision Making in Psychiatry and
the Law, Baltimore: Williams & Wilkins, pp 113-132-Ed.)
The authors gratefully acknowledge the contributions of David Barnard,
Ph.D., and Leslie M. Levi.
Drs. Bursztajn and Gutheil and Mr. Brodsky and Ms. Levi are associated
with the Program in Psychiatry and the Law, of the department of psychiatry
at Massachusetts Mental Health Center.
Dr. Barnard is associated with the Institute for the Medical Humanities
at the University of Texas Medical Branch in Galveston.
References
-
Bettelheim B (1960), The
Informed Heart; Autonomy in a Mass Rage. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
-
Bursztajn H, Feinbloom RI,
Hamm RM, Brodsky A (1981), Medical Choices,
Medical Chances: How Patients, Families and Physicians Can Cope with
Uncertainty. New York: Delacorte/Lawrence.
-
Calabresi G, Bobbitt P (1978),
Tragic Choices. New York: Norton.
-
Chanowitz B, Langer EJ (1981),
Premature cognitive commitment. J Pers Soc Psychol 41(6):1051-1063.
-
Childress JF (1978), Rationing
of medical treatment. In: The Encyclopedia of Bioethics, Reich WT,
ed. New York: Free Press, pp 1414-1419.
-
Chodoff P (1980), Psychotherapy
of the survivor. In: Survivors, Victims and Perpetrators: Essays
on the Nazi Holocaust, Dimsdale JE, ed. Washington, D.C.: Hemisphere,
pp 205-218.
-
Day M (1981), Process in classical psychodynamic
groups. Int J Group Psychother 31(2):153-174.
-
Des Pres T (1976), The Survivor:
An Anatomy of Life in the Death Camps. New York: Oxford University
Press.
-
Deutsch H (1965), Some forms of
emotional disturbance and their relationship to schizophrenia (1942).
In: Neuroses and Character Types: Clinical Psychoanalytic Studies.
New York: International Universities Press, pp 262-281.
-
Edelwich J, Brodsky A (1980),
Burnout: Stages of Disillusionment in the Helping Professions. New
York: Human Sciences Press.
-
Freud S (1957), On narcissism: an
introduction (1914). In: Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological
Works of Sigmund Freud, Vol. 14, Strachey J, ed. London: Hogarth
Press, pp 73-102.
-
Groves JE (1978), Taking care of
the hateful patient. N Engl J Med 298(16):883-887.
-
Gutheil TG (1977), Ideology
as resistance: a supervisory challenge. Psychiatr Q 49(2):88-96.
-
Gutheil TG (1979), Legal defense
as ego defense: a special form of resistance to the therapeutic process.
Psychiatr Q 51(4):251-256.
-
Hamm RM, Bursztajn HJ, Appelbaum PS
et al. (1983), Regression and introspection in the analysis of clinical
decision making: the case of the three-day paper. Presented at the
First International Congress for Psychiatry, Ethics and the Law,
Haifa, Israel.
-
Havens LL (1965), The anatomy of
a suicide. N Engl J Med 272:401-406.
-
Klein M (1975), Notes on some schizoid
mechanisms (1946). In: Envy and Gratitude and Other Works. New York:
Delacorte/Lawrence, pp. 1-24.
-
Lucas GR Jr. (1975), Triage in Medicine
and Society. Vol. III: Inquiries in Medical Ethics. Houston: Institute
of Religion and Human Development.
-
Maltsberger JT, Buie DH
(1974), Countertransference hate in the treatment of suicidal patients.
Arch Gen Psychiatry 30(5):625-633.
-
Modell AH (in press) Self-preservation
and the preservation of the self. Annu Psychoanal.
-
Motto JA, Heilbron DC, Juster RP,
Bostrom AG (1981), Suicide risk assessment: development of a clinical
instrument. In: Proceedings, Fourteenth Annual Meeting, American
Association of Suicidology. Albuquerque, N.M.
-
O'Donnell TJ (1960), The morality
of triage. Georgetown Med Bull 14:68-71.
-
O'Keefe DL (1982), Stolen Lightning:
The Social Theory of Magic. New York: Continuum.
-
President's Commission for
the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical Research
(1983), Securing Access to Health Care: A Report on the Ethical Implications
of Differences in the Availability of Health Services. Ethical Implications
of Differences in the Availability of Health Services. Washington,
D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office.
-
Rawls J (1971), A Theory of Justice.
Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
-
Rund DA, Rausch TS (1981), Triage. St.
Louis: Mosby.
-
Russell A (1980), Late effects
influence on the children of the concentration camp survivor. In:
Survivors, Victims and Perpetrators: Essays on the Nazi Holocaust,
Dimsdale JE, ed. Washington, D.C.: Hemisphere, pp 175-204.
-
Schreter RK, Sharfstein SS,
Schreter CA (1997), Managing Care, Not Dollars: The Continuum of
Mental Health Services. Washington, D.C.: American Psychiatric Press.
-
Sloman L (1981), Intrafamilial struggles
for power: an ethological perspective. J Fam Psychiatry 2:13-33.
-
U. S. Department of
Defense (1975), Emergency War Surgery. 1st U.S. Revision of the Emergency
War Surgery NATO Handbook. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing
Office, pp 153.
-
Vickery DM (1975), Triage: Problem-oriented
Sorting of Patients. Bowie, Md.: Brady.
-
White EB (1977), Bedfellow. In: Essays
of E.B. White. New York: Harper & Row, pp 80-89.
-
Winnicott DW (1965), Hospital
care supplementing intensive psychotherapy in adolescence. In: The
Maturational Processes and the Facilitating Environment; Studies
in the Theory of Emotional Development. New York: International Universities
Press, pp 242-248.
-
Winslow GR (1982), Triage and
Justice. Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press.
-
Yalom ID (1975), The Theory and Practice
of Group Psychotherapy, 2nd ed. New York: Basic Books.